Does the Universe have a Hard Drive?

1 downloads 189 Views 350KB Size Report
Jan 25, 2017 - Free University of Tbilisi, Business School & School of Physics. 240, David Agmashenebeli ... sor at
Does the Universe have a Hard Drive? Zura Kakushadze§†1 §

arXiv:1701.07161v1 [physics.pop-ph] 25 Jan 2017



Quantigicr Solutions LLC 1127 High Ridge Road #135, Stamford, CT 06905 2 Free University of Tbilisi, Business School & School of Physics 240, David Agmashenebeli Alley, Tbilisi, 0159, Georgia (December 3, 2016)

Abstract We discuss an apparent information paradox that arises in a materialist’s description of the Universe if we assume that the Universe is 100% quantum. We discuss possible ways out of the paradox, including that Laws of Nature are not purely deterministic, or that gravity is classical. Our observation of the paradox stems from an interdisciplinary thought process whereby the Universe can be viewed as a “quantum computer”. Our presentation is intentionally nontechnical to make it accessible to as wide a readership base as possible.

1

Zura Kakushadze, Ph.D., is the President of Quantigicr Solutions LLC, an Adjunct Professor at the University of Connecticut, and a Full Professor at Free University of Tbilisi. Email: [email protected] 2 DISCLAIMER: This address is used by the corresponding author for no purpose other than to indicate his professional affiliation as is customary in publications. In particular, the contents of this paper are not intended as an investment, legal, tax or any other such advice, and in no way represent views of Quantigic Solutions LLC, the website www.quantigic.com or any of their other affiliates.

Every time you start up your laptop, tablet or smart phone, its operating system3 – which sets the rules by which your device functions – is loaded from a hard drive, where the operating system is stored, to its memory, where various processes run and computations are performed (for a schematic depiction, see Figure 1). Laws of Nature – i.e., the laws of physics – are analogous to an operating system by which the Universe functions. Thus, (almost)4 everything we observe appears to be described by four fundamental forces: gravity, electromagnetism, weak and strong interactions.5 The latter three, together with the known subatomic particles,6 are described by the Standard Model of particle physics [Particle Data Group, 2016].7 Theoretically, the laws of physics are postulated. Then they are verified experimentally. These laws contain a nonzero amount of information, i.e., there is more than 0 bits of information encoded in them. Thus, if we, say, write down Einstein’s celebrated mass-energy relation8 E = m c2 ,

(1)

this expression contains a nontrivial amount of information. So do all laws of physics we currently believe to describe Nature, including the Standard Model, Einstein’s General Relativity, etc.9 This compels us to ask the following question: How (where) does the Universe store the information encoded in the laws of physics? This is by far not a rhetorical question. In a materialist’s10 description of Nature, any nontrivial amount of information – including that encoded in the laws of physics – must somehow be stored (be it in the form of matter or energy), just as an operating system is stored on your laptop’s or smart phone’s hard drive. From this (i.e., the materialist’s) standpoint, it would be a copout – unappealing both 3

E.g., Linux, Windows, iOS, etc. There are things we still do not quite understand, e.g., the nature of dark matter, where the dark energy (a.k.a. the cosmological constant) comes from, how gravity fits in the quantum Universe (see below), etc. However, this does not affect the point we make herein. 5 The weak force is responsible for radioactive decay. The electromagnetic and weak interactions are unified into the electroweak force. The strong force binds quarks and gluons together inside protons, neutrons and nuclei comprised therefrom. 6 These are leptons (e.g., electrons and neutrinos) and quarks. There is also the Higgs particle. 7 Which is sometimes also referred to as “the theory of almost everything” [Oerter, 2006]. 8 E is energy, m is mass, and c is the speed of light in the vacuum. Here we could have written down, e.g., Newton’s second law F = m a (F is force, m is mass, and a is acceleration). However, perhaps somewhat ironically, it appears that most people would recognize Einstein’s E = m c2 [Einstein, 1905] before Newton’s F = m a [Newton, 1687]. 9 In the Standard Model one usually writes down its Lagrangian, which encodes classical propagation and interactions of various fundamental particles such as electrons, quarks, photons (quanta of light), etc., augmented with (the so-called quantum field theory) rules for computing quantum effects (via, e.g., path integral and Feynman diagrams [Feynman, 1949]). For gravity we still do not have an experimentally verified quantum theory (string theory being a candidate therefor; see, e.g., [Green et al, 2012]); however, Einstein’s General Relativity [Einstein, 1915] appears to accurately describe classical gravity and its Lagrangian too encodes a nontrivial amount of information. 10 That is, without resorting to a higher power of any kind. See, e.g., [Sagan, 2002]. 4

1

intellectually and scientifically – to simply state to the effect that “Laws of Nature are a property of the Universe”. And this is where an apparent paradox arises... On the fundamental level, our Universe is not deterministic but probabilistic – the Universe is quantum.11 Assuming the Universe is 100% quantum, i.e., all matter and interactions12 are described by a quantum theory, any information stored in the Universe cannot be purely deterministic but probabilistic. That is, the laws of physics apparently could not be deterministic. However, our description of the Universe via the laws of physics assumes that the latter are 100% deterministic... So, something’s got to give. One possibility is that the laws of physics are not deterministic but probabilistic. This would amount to a major shift in the existing paradigm. Another possibility is that not all matter or interactions are quantum. Based on their precision tests, which incorporate quantum corrections, it appears to be a safe bet to assume that the electroweak and strong interactions are quantum. However, despite theoretical arguments13 that gravity must also be quantum, currently there is no experimental evidence that gravity is in fact quantum, which stems from the extreme weakness of gravity (compared with other fundamental forces) at the microscopic level where quantum effects become relevant. So, perhaps one can consider a scenario where gravity is classical14 and the laws of physics are somehow encoded via gravity – albeit here we do not hold ourselves out to understand how this would be realized in detail. Yet another apparent possibility would be to declare that the laws of physics are what they are, and that we do not need to understand how the information encoded in them is stored.15 However, this would appear to abandon the aforesaid materialist’s standpoint – one can then simply call the unquestionable and almighty laws of physics “God” and be done with it...16 The upshot is that we appear to have a paradox if we take the materialist’s 11

This statement requires a qualification – see below. Including gravity – see below. 13 These are based on thought experiments such as those of [Eppley and Hannah, 1977] and [Page and Geilker, 1981], whose critiques appear, e.g., in [Mattingly, 2006] and [Hawkins, 1982], respectively. Thus, precisely due to the extreme weakness of gravity, to detect potential “ill-effects” of coupling quantum matter to classical gravity (e.g., indefinite dissipation of energy by quantum matter via classical gravitational radiation), it would appear to require a detector so massive that it would be inside its own Schwarzschild radius [Schwarzschield, 1916] (i.e., it would be a black hole), or detection might take much longer than the age of the Universe, etc. Here we will not delve into such controversy but simply note that, notwithstanding any (important) theoretical considerations, physics is an experimental science. 14 Again, notwithstanding the aforesaid theoretical arguments to the contrary. 15 Here one can kick the can down the road by invoking the string landscape approach [Susskind, 2003], whereby, in a presumably unified string theory description, different looking universes – including our Universe – arise as different vacua, i.e., solutions to the string equations of motion. However, such a description itself encodes a nontrivial amount of information (e.g., in the form of the aforesaid string equations of motion), and assuming that string theory is quantum, we are still facing the same paradox, albeit perhaps on a deeper level. Furthermore, the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics [Everett, 1957] does not appear to alleviate the paradox. 16 And here we by no means suggest that this is not the right approach. After all, arguendo, this would appear to bode well with G¨odel’s incompleteness theorems [G¨odel, 1931]. 12

2

approach and assume that the Universe is 100% quantum. The purpose of this note is to point out the paradox, not to resolve it. In this regard, we could simply conclude here. However, the paradox appears to run even deeper in the context of the Big Bang framework [Lemaˆıtre, 1931], whereby our Universe was created about 14 billion years ago out of “nothing” (vacuum). A priori there is no issue with creating matter and interactions out of “nothing”: matter carries positive (kinetic) energy, while gravity supplies negative (potential) energy, the total energy is zero and is therefore conserved when the Universe is created from “nothing”. However, the nonzero bits of information encoded in the laws of physics would have to be created out of “nothing” within the Big Bang framework. Conceptually, this appears to be just as unappealing as the information loss paradox in the context of black hole evaporation via Hawking radiation (a quantum effect...) [Hawking, 1974] – “structured” information (pure quantum state) encoded in the matter falling into a black hole is transformed into “unstructured” information (mixed quantum state) carried by Hawking radiation (a.k.a. non-unitary evolution). Is creating structured information out of thin air any better conceptually than such information loss? We do not know the answer(s) to the question(s) we raise herein. However, we believe raising them is warranted. Thinking about the laws of physics as encoding a nonzero amount of information is a very “computer science” thing to do. In fact, we can think about the apparent paradox we describe in this note in the context of computer science. If we think about the Universe as a “quantum computer” (cf. [Lloyd, 2012]), we still need purely deterministic (classical) code – i.e., the laws of physics – to run it, which is how actual quantum computers work. The underlying physical processes in quantum computers are quantum, but the code is 100% deterministic [Feynman, 1982]. In this regard, finally, let us mention yet another possible way out of the aforesaid paradox: the simulation hypothesis [Bostrom, 2003], whereby our Universe is simply a computer simulation run by “other beings”. However, while the simulation hypothesis, arguendo, may not necessarily invalidate the scientific method (see, e.g., [Beane et al, 2012]), it does appear to kick the can down the road as we essentially have no way of describing the universe in which the “other beings” live and run their curious simulations...

Acknowledgments I would like to thank Alberto Iglesias and Willie Yu for invaluable discussions and encouragement.

References Beane, S., Davoudi, Z. and Savage, M.J. (2012) Constraints on the Universe as a Numerical Simulation. arXiv:1210.1847.

3

Bostrom, N. (2003) Are You Living in a Computer Simulation? The Philosophical Quarterly 53(211): 243-255. Einstein, A. (1905) Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter K¨orper. Annalen der Physik 322(10): 891-921. Einstein, A. (1915) Die Feldgleichungen der Gravitation. Sitzungsberichte der Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften, pp. 844-847. Eppley, K. and Hannah, E. (1977) The necessity of quantizing the gravitational field. Foundations of Physics 7(1): 51-68. Everett, H. (1957) “Relative State” Formulation of Quantum Mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics 29(3): 454-462. Feynman, R.P. (1949) Space-Time Approach to Quantum Electrodynamics. Phys. Rev. 76(6): 769-789. Feynman, R.P. (1982) Simulating physics with computers. International Journal of Theoretical Physics 21(6-7): 467-488. ¨ G¨odel, K. (1931) Uber formal unentscheidbare S¨atze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme, I. Monatshefte f¨ ur Mathematik und Physik 38(1): 173198. Green, M., Schwarz, J. and Witten, E. (2012) Superstring theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Hawking, S.W. (1974) Black hole explosions? Nature 248(5443): 30-31. Hawkins, B. (1982) Indirect Evidence for Quantum Gravity? Phys. Rev. Lett. 48(7): 520. Lemaˆıtre, G. (1931) The Evolution of the Universe: 128(3234): 699-701.

Discussion. Nature

Lloyd, S. (2012) The universe as quantum computer. In: Zenil, H. (ed.) A Computable Universe: Understanding and exploring Nature as computation. Singapore: World Scientific. Mattingly, J. (2006) Why Eppley and Hannah’s thought experiment fails. Phys. Rev. D 73(6): 064025. Newton, I. (1687) Philosophiæ naturalis principia mathematica. Londini: Jussu Societatis Regiæ ac Typis Josephi Streater. Oerter, R. (2006) The Theory of Almost Everything: The Standard Model, the Unsung Triumph of Modern Physics. New York, NY: Plume (Penguin Group), 336 pp. 4

Page, D.N. and Geilker, C.D. (1981) Indirect Evidence for Quantum Gravity. Phys. Rev. Lett. 47(14): 979-982. Patrignani, C. et al (Particle Data Group) (2016) Chin. Phys. C40: 100001. Sagan, C. (2002) Cosmos. New York, NY: Random House, 384 pp. ¨ Schwarzschild, K. (1916) Uber das Gravitationsfeld eines Massenpunktes nach der Einsteinschen Theorie. Sitzungsberichte der Deutschen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin, Klasse fur Mathematik, Physik, und Technik, pp. 189196. Susskind, L. (2003) The anthropic landscape of string theory. arXiv:hepth/0302219.

Hard Drive OS OS

RAM OS

CPU

Figure 1. OS = Operating System. RAM = Random Access Memory. CPU = Central Processing Unit. RAM is the volatile memory space that stores the data directly accessed by CPU. OS is installed and stored on the Hard Drive (HD). The first software to run upon startup is BIOS (Basic Input/Output System), which loads OS into RAM from HD.

5